(c) 2017 by Barton Paul Levenson
Now that we have the conditional and biconditional operators (→, ↔), we can state some very useful equivalences using them. Rules using the conditional are "tautological implications," while those using the biconditional are "tautological equivalences." The first tautological implication is called Modus Ponens:
[(p → q) ∧ p] → q
This enables us to set up a nice syllogism:
M: If the Earth is about to blow up, we're all doomed.
m: The Earth is about to blow up.
C: We're all doomed.
p → q
p
———
∴ q
As opposed to putting all of a sequence of logical statements on the same line, putting them one to a line is putting them in "argument format." The underlining separates premises from conclusion; the ∴ is not so much a "conclusion operator" as a smug little "so there" symbol. Logicians aren't above the awful vice of pride.
Here's another useful tautology, Modus Tollens:
[(p → q) ∧ ¬q] → ¬p
A syllogism using it runs:
Syllogism format | Argument format |
---|---|
M: If I love sociology, I'll get an A. m: I didn't get an A. C: I must not love sociology. |
p → q ¬q ——————— ∴ ¬p |
Syllogism format | Argument format |
---|---|
M: The sky is blue. C: So either the sky is blue, or the Moon is pink. |
p ——————— ∴ p ∨ q |
This is right: | p → (p ∨ q) |
These are wrong: | p → (p ∧ q) (p ∨ q) → p |
The next rule is called the disjunctive syllogism:
[(p ∨ q) ∧ (¬p)] → q
[(p ∨ q) ∧ (¬q)] → p
Or in English, if either case A, or case B, must be true, and we know one is false, the other must be true. Obviously.
Here's an example:
Syllogism format | Argument format |
---|---|
M: Either Mr. Green or Mrs. White is the murderer. m: It isn't Mrs. White. C: It darn well had to be Mr. Green. |
p ∨ q ¬q ——————— ∴ p |
Syllogism format | Argument format |
---|---|
M: Shooting Bob in the heart made his heart stop. m: Bob's heart stopping caused his death. C: Shooting Bob in the heart killed him. |
p → q q → r ——————— ∴ p → r |
Law | Statement |
---|---|
Double Negation | ¬¬p ↔ p |
Commutative | p ∧ q ↔ q ∧ p p ∨ q ↔ q ∨ p |
Associative | (p ∧ q) ∧ r ↔ p ∧ (q ∧ r) (p ∨ q) ∨ r ↔ p ∨ (q ∨ r) |
DeMorgan's | ¬(p ∧ q) ↔ (¬p) ∨ (¬q) ¬(p ∨ q) ↔ (¬p) ∧ (¬q) |
Distributive | p ∧ (q ∨ r) ↔ (p ∧ q) ∨ (p ∧ r) p ∨ (q ∧ r) ↔ (p ∨ q) ∧ (p ∨ r) |
Absorption or Idempotent | p ∧ p ↔ p p ∨ p ↔ p |
Switcheroo* | (p → q) ↔ ((¬p) ∨ q) |
Modus Ponens | [(p → q) ∧ p] → q |
Modus Tollens | [(p → q) ∧ ¬q] → ¬p |
Simplification | (p ∧ q) → p (p ∧ q) → q |
Addition | p → (p ∨ q) |
Disjunctive Syllogism | [(p ∨ q) ∧ (¬p)] → q [(p ∨ q) ∧ (¬q)] → p |
Transitivity | [(p → q) ∧ (q → p)] → (p → r) |
*There has got to be a better name for the seventh law listed above than "Switcheroo Law." If anyone knows it, please e-mail me at levenson1960@gmail.com and let me know. Thanks!
Lastly, here's a table of logical operators in the propositional calculus. The last one is needed only when doing multi-line arguments in argument format:
symbol | meaning |
---|---|
∧ | and |
∨ | or |
¬ | not |
≡ | eqv (is equivalent to) |
→ | imp (implies) |
↔ | iff (if and only if) |
∴ | thus or therefore |
Page created: | 04/04/2017 |
Last modified: | 04/05/2017 |
Author: | BPL |